Grotius, Hugo

(redirected from Grotius)
Also found in: Dictionary, Thesaurus, Encyclopedia, Wikipedia.
Related to Grotius: Pufendorf

Grotius, Hugo

Hugo Grotius. LIBRARY OF CONGRESS
Hugo Grotius.
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS

Hugo Grotius, also known as Huigh de Groot, achieved prominence as a Dutch jurist and statesman and is regarded as the originator of International Law.

Grotius was born April 10, 1583, in Delft, Netherlands. A brilliant student, Grotius attended the University of Leiden, received a law degree at the age of fifteen, and was admitted to the bar and began his legal practice at Delft in 1599. It was at this time that he became interested in international law, and, in 1609, wrote a preliminary piece titled Mare liberum, which advocated freedom of the seas to all countries.

In 1615, Grotius became involved in a religious controversy between two opposing groups, the Remonstrants, Dutch Protestants who abandoned Calvinism to follow the precepts of their leader, Jacobus Arminius, and the Anti-Remonstrants, who adhered to the beliefs of Calvinism. The dispute extended to politics, and when Maurice of Nassau gained control of the government, the Remonstrants lost popular support. Grotius, a supporter of the Remonstrants, was imprisoned in 1619. Two years later he escaped, seeking safety in Paris.

In Paris, Grotius began his legal writing, and, in 1625, produced De jure belli ac pacis, translated as "Concerning the Law of War and Peace." This work is regarded as the first official text of the principles of international law, wherein Grotius maintained that Natural Law is the basis for legislation for countries as well as individuals. He opposed war in all but extreme cases and advocated respect for life and the ownership of property. The main sources for his theories were the Bible and history.

"What the consent of all men makes known as their will is law."
—Hugo Grotius

Grotius spent the remainder of his years in diplomatic and theological endeavors. From 1635 to 1645, he represented Queen Christina of Sweden as her ambassador to France. He pursued his religious interests and wrote several theological works. Grotius died August 28, 1645, in Rostock, Germany.

Mentioned in ?
References in periodicals archive ?
83) William Welwod, An Abridgement of All Sea-Lawes (London, 1613, STC 25237), 61-72; Hugo Grotius, `Defensio Capitis Quinti Maris Liberi Oppugnati a Guilielmo Welwodo .
With his depiction of man's dominion over the earth as God's gift, Grotius makes clear that the earth is for the use of human beings.
Grotius, too, explained that treaties constituted "the perfect
Compreender bem Wolff exige conhecer a tradicao do jusnaturalismo racionalista que o precedeu, especialmente Grotius, Pufendorf e Thomasius.
The Greek model will inspire not only Cruce and Sully, but also Grotius, the abbot Saint Pierre, Jean Jacques Rousseau, Immanuel Kant, and even Simon Bolivar, architect of the Amphictyonic Congress in Panama in 1826.
Eva van Hooijdonk extends this approach to the collection of Latin epigrams on Prince Maurice of Nassau that Hugo Grotius composed around 1600 to accompany a series of engravings depicting various Dutch successes in the revolt against the Spanish.
Larry May's chapter on war crimes trials includes some substantial arguments, although it gets off to a weak start by drawing extensively on Hugo Grotius to support the argument.
IR scholars will also find familiar terrain in discussions of Risse's central interlocutor: seventeenth-century international jurist Hugo Grotius, whose ideas about humanity's common ownership of the earth are recruited in support of his position.
Central to the argument is the considerations of iuirisprudentia and modern natural law as founded by Hugo Grotius and Samuel van Pufendorf in relation to such themes as religious pluralism in the State; the definition of the obligations and limits of legislation, and the rights of sovereign power in religion; the rejection of the confessional State and the use of force against revolutionary movements of the human conscience; the justification of the right to resist; and the elaboration of the characteristics and limits of the new notion of civil tolerance (derived from the voluntaristic and anti-Hobbesian perspective of Barbeyrac in his commentary on Pufendorf using Locke's work and the theory of obligation).