Aristotle

(redirected from Aristotelians)
Also found in: Dictionary, Thesaurus, Medical, Encyclopedia.

Aristotle

Aristotle. LIBRARY OF CONGRESS
Aristotle.
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS

Aristotle was born in 384 b.c., in Stagira, Greece. He achieved prominence as an eminent philosopher who greatly influenced the basic principles of philosophy and whose ideologies are still practiced today.

Aristotle was a student of the renowned philosopher Plato and tutored Alexander the Great, who became King of Macedonia in 336 b.c.

Aristotle established his own school in the Lyceum, near Athens, in 335 b.c. He often lectured his students in the portico, or walking place, of the Lyceum. The school was subsequently called Peripatetic, after the Greek word peripatos for "walking place."

In 323 b.c. the reign of Alexander ended with his death, and Aristotle sought refuge at Chalcis.

Aristotle formulated numerous beliefs about the reasoning power of humans and the essence of being. He stressed the importance of nature and instructed his pupils to closely study natural phenomena. When teaching science, he believed that all ideas must be supported by explanations based upon facts.

Concerning the realm of politics, Aristotle propounded that humans are inherently political and demonstrate an essential part of their humanity when participating in civic affairs.

Philosophy was a subject of great interest to Aristotle, and he theorized that philosophy was the foundation of the ability to understand the basic axioms that comprise knowledge. In order to study and question completely, Aristotle viewed logic as the basic means of reasoning. To think logically, one had to apply the syllogism, which was a form of thought comprised of two premises that led to a conclusion; Aristotle taught that this form can be applied to all logical reasoning.

"Man is by nature a political animal."
—Aristotle

To understand reality, Aristotle theorized that it must be categorized as substance, quality, quantity, relation, determination in time and space, action, passion or passivity, position, and condition. To know and understand the reality of an object required an explanation of its material cause, which is why it exists or its composition; its formal cause, or its design; its efficient cause, or its creator; and its final cause, or its reason for being.

Aristotle agreed with his mentor, Plato, concerning the field of ethics. The goodness of a being depended upon the extent to which that being achieved its highest potential. For humans, the ultimate good is the continual use and development of their reasoning powers to fullest capacity. To effect fulfillment and contentment, humans must follow a life of contemplation, rather than pleasure.

The fundamental source of Aristotle's theories were his lectures to his students, which were compiled into several volumes. They include Organum, which discusses logic; Physics; Metaphysics; De Anima, concerning the soul; Rhetoric; Politics; Nichomachean Ethics and Eudemian Ethics, involving principles of conduct; and De Poetica, or poetics.

He also wrote Constitution of Athens, a description of the foundations of the government of Athens. The work was discovered in the late nineteenth century.

Aristotle died in 322 b.c., in Chalcis, Greece.

References in periodicals archive ?
intuitable--front-and-center for philosophy, as is typical for Aristotelian thinkers, with the justification that it is how we intuit the world.
Now Aristotelians can happily grant that virtue does not always benefit us, since a virtuous act can impede future virtuous activity, say by crippling or killing the agent.
What Yu shows is that in both Aristotelian and Confucian ethics goodness is identified with the development of humanity's natural potential.
According to the first interpretation, al-Kindi comes across as a Muslim who represents the Aristotelian tradition of neo-Platonism--that is, a philosopher of a doubly-late antiquity.
In the conventional and predominantly Thomistic view, as articulated by Bonnie Kent in this engaging study, the rediscovery of Aristotle's ethical and political works profoundly reshaped the history of Western moral thought, in large part because of the extraordinarily creative synthesis of Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity by Thomas Aquinas.
The most direct reason for taking an Aristotelian realist view of properties is that we perceive them.
Neither the Catholic end nor the Aristotelian means of Newman's argument have rendered it useless to theorists of the modern secular university.
Heidegger seeks at this time--and here all scholars are in agreement--a genuine form of life that goes beyond the traditional Aristotelian opposition between "theory" and "praxis.
Likewise, although he calls them Aristotelians, he shows natural philosophers abandoning some Peripatetic explanations.
The present collection includes several analyses of truly solid Aristotelians.
Perhaps, Stone concludes, the person who would have been most vindicated by this development was Peter Ramus (1515-1572) who was denied a prized chair in ethics at Heidelberg by the Aristotelians there as well as a teaching position at the Geneva Academ y by Theodore Beza.