Kant, Immanuel

(redirected from Kantianism)
Also found in: Dictionary, Thesaurus, Encyclopedia, Wikipedia.

Kant, Immanuel

Immanuel Kant. LIBRARY OF CONGRESS
Immanuel Kant.
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS

Immanuel Kant shook the foundations of Western philosophy in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. This author and professor did his most important writing between 1781 and 1790 while working at the University of Königsberg, where he spent most of his life. Kant's philosophical model not only swept aside the ideas of the so-called empiricists and rationalists who came before him, it also had a lasting effect outside of philosophy, especially in the areas of ethics and the law. Today, legal scholars still debate his ideas—and their sometimes startling implications—in relation to contemporary issues.

Kant was born into a lower-middle-class family in East Prussia in 1724. A gifted student, he studied in a Latin school from age eight until age sixteen, when he entered the University of Königsberg to take up theology, natural science, and philosophy. The death of his father forced him to abandon his studies in order to work as a private tutor, and he had to wait several years before returning to complete his education. By that time he was already writing serious books. From what is called Kant's precritical period, these early works are primarily scientific. In recognition of his talents, the university made him a lecturer and eventually a professor. He taught logic and metaphysics.

Twenty years later Kant attacked the reigning schools of thought. In this so-called critical period, he wrote his most famous book, The Critique of Pure Reason (1781). Kant's work examined the relation of experience and perception: he was concerned with how people know what they know, and just as important, the proper uses of the powers of reasoning. He argued that reality can be perceived only to the extent that it complies with the aptitude of the mind that is doing the perceiving. This places one kind of limitation on what can be known. Kant saw another limitation, too: only phenomena—things that can be experienced—are capable of being understood; everything else is unknown. The human senses, therefore, take supreme precedence in determining what is real.

These theories have implications for conventional morality. Kant viewed God, freedom, and immortality as incomprehensible: they can only be contemplated; their existence can never be proved. Nonetheless, he argued, all three of them are important as the basis for morality. Kant believed that reason is insufficient to justify moral behavior. The justification for behaving morally has to come from people's sense of duty, which he called the categorical imperative.

Kant continued to develop his philosophy in subsequent books including Critique of Judgment (1790) and Religion within the Limits of Reasons Alone (1793). The latter enraged the government, resulting in its Censorship and an official order to Kant to write no more books about religion.

"The greatest problem for the human species, the solution of which nature compels him to seek, is that of attaining a civil society which can administer justice universally."
—Immanuel Kant

Philosophers have studied Kant's work for over two centuries, but legal thinkers outside of Europe have only widely treated it in recent years. In the late twentieth century, when many U.S. scholars of law turned to interdisciplinary studies that involved the fields of economics and textual analysis, Kant provided another model for argument. Kant's ideas cover the foundation of law while specifically addressing property, contracts, and criminal punishment. Kant proposed that punishment should be meted out strictly without exception—because of society's duty to seek retribution. "[I]f justice goes," Kant wrote in 1797, "there is no longer any value in men's living on the earth."

Further readings

Fletcher, George P. 1987. "Why Kant." Columbia Law Review 87 (April).

Gillroy, John Martin. 2000. Justice & Nature: Kantian Philosophy, Environmental Policy & the Law. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown Univ. Press.

Goodrich, Peter. 2001. "Barron's Complaint: A Response to "Feminism, Aestheticism and the Limits of Law." Feminist Legal Studies 9 (August): 149–70.

Kant, Immanuel. 1991. "Metaphysical First Principles of the Doctrine of Right." In The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge Univ. Press.

Tunick, Mark. 1998. Practices and Principles: Approaches to Ethical and Legal Judgment. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton Univ. Press.

Waldron, Jeremy. 1996. "Kant's Legal Positivism." Harvard Law Review 109 (May).

Wright, R. George. 2002. "Treating Persons as Ends in Themselves; the Legal Implications of a Kantian Principle. University of Richmond Law Review 36, (March): 271–326.

Cross-references

Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich; Jurisprudence.

References in periodicals archive ?
For Tocqueville, it is no accident that McCloskey feels the need to fight so hard against the ethical monism of Kantianism, utilitarianism, and social contract theory.
Ross's prima facie duties, Asimov's laws of robotics, the Ten Commandments, and Kantianism. (220) This Part focuses on the theory of ethics created by the most famous deontologist, Immanuel Kant.
Since Foucault has disdainfully refused the "'blackmail of the Enlightenment", the simplistic imputation of "being for or against the Enlightenment" (Foucault 1984a, 45), it would be useless to introduce what we may call the "blackmail of Kant", reducing his philosophical position to a somewhat encapsulating and unresolved acceptance of Kantianism. More fruitful would be an interrogation of Foucault's intricate and oxymoronic relationship with both Kant and Nietzsche, with Western modernity and its inner and outer outsides (the genealogical unthought and the non-European geopolitical forces of displacement).
Utilitarianism and Kantianism may converge in the choice of programs of civic education, but they will often suggest different ways of implementing them
Held argues that the ethics of care, while still very new compared to its major philosophical alternatives (Kantianism, utilitarianism, and Aristotelian virtue ethics), nonetheless offers a viable alternative to all of them.
Several contributors respond decidedly in favor of America's engagement in what Professor Stephen Webb calls 'evangelical Kantianism.' In Webb's view, the role of America is to spread democracy throughout the world.
Richards relates the turmoil of personalities and relationships in early Romanticism, particularly the impact of the deaths of Sophie von Kuhn and of Auguste Bohmer on Novalis and Schelling respectively; but he also offers accounts of the transcendental idealism of Fichte's Wissenschaflslehre--'Kantianism properly understood', so Fichte maintained--and of Schelling's Naturphilosophie and Identitats-philosophie, a fundamental feature of which, Richards claims, is the idea of 'organicism', that is, 'the idea that consciousness and, consequently, nature have a fundamentally organic structure' (p.
Consequentialism, Kantianism, justice, and casuistry are a few types of moral philosophy and ethical theory.
(7.) According to Tihanov, in Heidelberg Aesthetics, "Lukacs presents a more elaborate, if not completely enthusiastic, case for a Hegelian understanding of culture as a possible alternative to Kantianism" (Tihanov, p.
Of course, Kantianism validates only ethical mandates.
I will leave it for others to determine whether this alternative position is best construed as a revision to, or rejection of, Kantianism. My aim is simply to show that the position, whatever its name, makes better sense than orthodox understandings of Kantianism, not only because it is grounded in a coherent and unequivocal notion of maxims, but also because it is proof against some of the most telling objections that virtue ethicists and others have leveled against Kantianism.